1. The aim of this work is to shed light on how Walter Benjamin’s concept of history
is addressed to politics, and concomitantly, how politics is referred to ethics. Benjamin’s texts contain many passages
concerning politics and ethics, but one searches in vain for a systematically developed political ethics. The rudiments
of those passages could be summarized, but that would not thereby adequately elucidate Benjamin’s ethico-political thought,
and then one would inevitably stagnate its potentiality. It is well-known Benjamin’s game of hide-and-seek in his philosophical
texts, so any attempt to read Benjamin in such a way that the relevant passages open one’s understanding to a systematically
oriented political ethics must rely upon other approaches. For my own part, I draw heavily on Reyes Mate’s La
Razon de los Vencidos [Barcelona: Anthropos, 1991].
What does Benjamin’s philosophy of history involve? What is hidden behind the veil of Benjamin’s theological-philosophical
language? A straightforward answer would be its political content. However, the answer to the question might be twofold: one
side of the answer concerns an epistemological key - the true knowledge of history becomes self-knowledge of the subject -
and the other side, concerns an ethical key – the impulse of political action is experience.
First, the core of Benjamin’s philosophy of history is a new concept of the present, and correspondingly, a new
constitution of ‘the subject of historical knowledge.’ For Benjamin, the subject of history is the ‘struggling,
oppressed class itself,’ [Benjamin 1940, thesis XII, 394] oppressed class that becomes itself a subject of history not
by taking up arms, but by putting the stress on historical knowledge and itself –‘what is historically understood
contains time in its interior as a precious but tasteless seed’ [Ibid, thesis XVII, 396]. The subject
of history is not given; on the contrary, it has to constitute itself as the depository and catalyst of historical knowledge.
This process of constitution is nourished not from utopias – ‘the ideal of liberated grandchildren’ - but
from remembrances and experiences – ‘the image of enslaved ancestors’ [Ibid, thesis XII, 394.]
The ‘oppressed class’ does not become a subject of history because of its place in the productive process,
like Marx’s subject of revolution - the working class - which constitutes its real power from its productive position,
but rather passing ‘through what has been, in order to experience the present,’ [Benjamin 1927-40, 838, Fº,6]
that is, through the actualization (remembrance) of the past – ‘the awakening of a not-yet-conscious knowledge
of what has been’ [Ibid, 458, N1,9]. Thus historical knowledge is an encounter between a subject that does not
resign himself to the given as real - ‘the ‘eternal’ image of the past’ [Benjamin 1940, thesis XVI,
396] - and a specific past as not present – ‘[a] time [not] filled full by the now-time (Jetztzeit)’
[Ibid, thesis XIV, 395] - that is, between a dissatisfied subject and an
unknown object.
Once the ‘oppressed class’ has grasped this knowledge – ‘Articulating the past historically…
means appropriating a memory as it flashes up in a moment of danger’ [Ibid, thesis VI, 391] and recognizes the
sign of ‘a revolutionary chance in the fight for the oppressed past,’ [Benjamin 1940, thesis XVII, 396] then it
could introduce a critical change into its present situation. However, its action would never be the same as Marx’s
revolutionary class, whose action is grounded on its power, rather it would be its weakness, its necessity.
For Benjamin the
notion of necessity refers to an instance of dissociation between the subject and its historical situation. Thus, the answer
to that necessity is the actualization of the past that has not been realized; or to put it differently, by the apprehension
of that forgotten past the subject grasps his historical consciousness, a new consciousness of himself, for hitherto the subject
has experienced necessity as a mere privation, not as an impulse to strive ‘for the oppressed past.’ A
past that enriches the present and awakes the forgotten meaning within it – his ‘tradition’, the meaning
of his hope - a past that recovers, in the very core of the present, a new actuality. That is because historical ‘truth
is not […] a merely contingent function of knowing, but is bound to a nucleus of time lying hidden within the knower
and the known alike’ [Ibid, 463, N3,2]. Here the consciousness of necessity is double: first, the necessity of
happiness - ‘the idea of redemption’ - that it lacks, and second, the consciousness that the power to fulfill
it comes from the past – ‘we have been endowed with a weak messianic
power, a power on which the past has a claim’ [Benjamin 1940, thesis II, 390].
According to Benjamin, there is only a subject of history if the candidate to accomplish the role is invested by a
knowledge that is received from the past. This mediation of knowledge in the constitution of the subject of history seems
to paralyze the subject’s action, but it does not because the motives for action - necessities and values - are never
given before the constitution of the subject, who then - not before - assumes them as the aims of his political action.
Second, Benjamin’s political pathway seeks for something that is not given at the beginning of the process, but
discovers the impulse that leads to the end - ‘remembrance.’ Benjamin understands politics as the route from the
beginning to the end due to ethic, that is, an ethical impulse drives the process. The task of politics is to take to its
end, as much as possible, ‘what is good for men in general’ [Aristotle, NE, 1140b]. Thus, Benjamin conceives
political action as ‘the adequate form of morally and philosophically decisive action’ [Radnoti 1978, 66].
Can we consider the universality of history without the past that is not present? Can we think about the universality
of the present without ‘the oppressed past’? In Benjamin’s view, the ethical principle of universality is
the non-subject (the oppressed man) that in the dialectical point of explosion (awakening) discovers himself as a needed and
dissatisfied man: ‘the moment of awakening would be identical with the “now of recognizability,” in which
things put on their true […] face’ [Benjamin 1927-40, 463-4, N3a,3]. That is the impulse (dialectical negation)
that drives the non-subject to abandon his inhuman condition; impulse that charges itself with reason (ethical rationality)
when he discovers the non-identity (dissociation) with the present, that is, the present privation of the subject’s
dignity, freedom and equality. With the notion of ‘remembrance,’ then, Benjamin reconciles ethics and politics
in an original relationship:
History is […] a form of remembrance. What science has “determined,” remembrance can
modify. Such mindfulness can make the incomplete (happiness) into something complete, and the complete (suffering) into something
incomplete [Ibid, 471, N8,1].
Precisely, Benjamin’s ethics turns into politics beginning with the critical moment of the oppressed man, when
the non-subject is in tension to be a subject. That tension necessarily leads to a confrontation with the actual situation
of injustice, oppression and suffering. In Benjamin, the non-subject, because of his inhumanity, dialectically becomes the
subject; it is the notion of non-subjectivity that defines the human condition. Moreover, it is by dialectically assuming
that condition that man obtains his human condition - ‘In the principle
it’s the negation’ [Schelling 1856-41, 8:600]. But how in Benjamin is conceived that access to the condition
of the subject? The starting point is the recognition of the human condition, that is, the recognition of the other
as our own condition. Due to Benjamin radical claims of the universality of the subject, it is possible to speak of political
ethics.
2. Max Horkheimer claims that ‘man’s striving
for happiness is to be recognized as a natural fact requiring no justification’ [Horkheimer 1992, 44]. In the same way,
Benjamin bases the radical universality of human action on a verifiable fact. This factum
is the experience of feelings such as rebelliousness, compassion or solidarity; feelings that express the political dimension
of experience. In Horkheimer’s words:
The life of most people is so wretched, the deprivations and humiliations are so many, and their efforts
and success are for the most part so disproportionate, that we can easily understand the hope that the earthly order of things
may not be the only real one [Ibid, 23].
For Horkheimer, the ‘moral sentiment’ is active today in a twofold manner: first, as compassion, and second,
as politics. Likewise, Benjamin understands this experience as solidarity, which emerges from the notion of remembrance; solidarity
as the attitude that looks toward the other not because the power he holds - that feature admirable and admired by bourgeoisie
society - but for his potentiality to develop happiness. The experience as solidarity is guided to the other’s necessities
and wants. Thus the subject of experience sets his sights on the neediness and poverty of the present whose overcoming opens
the way to hope, and is addressed to happiness – ‘the idea of happiness is indissolubly bound up with the image
of redemption’ [Benjamin 1940, thesis II, 389]. We cannot understand this experience without the orientation toward
the realization of mankind; orientation that rises from the privation of the present, from the misery and suffering that predominates
in history. The experience of suffering is translated into a gesture of compassion to the other, who is not resigned to its
luck. This experience as solidarity is given as a vital necessity; no one questions its grounds or legitimacy: ‘All
living beings have a claim to happiness for which it would not in the least ask any justification or grounds’ [Horkheimer
1995, 34-5]. Thus, solidarity with the man forced to suffering and death is called compassion, a feeling that is inherent
to man.
However, the experience as solidarity is rationally mediated: the other is worthy of compassion. We view the other
not as a mere suffering object of a blind historical situation, but as a subject with his dignity offended and frustrated.
He is recognized as an end in itself, and not as a mere means. That dignity through which the other reveals himself is the
dignity that he justly demands. Therefore, compassion is the mediation between the particularity of that experience and the
universality of human dignity.
Compassion, though, is the ‘moral sentiment’ of an inter-subjective relationship, not a symmetrical one,
but one rather in accordance with a real asymmetry. If we view this relationship as ideally symmetrical, the question is just
to determine the object of compassion, the recipient of our compassion. Here it
is assumed that the ethical subject is already constituted. But the dignity that the other has, as the object of compassion, he really does not have it. What he has is a demand, a necessity, and a negation, as the
subject of compassion. Here the emphasis is not put on the object, but on the subject.
Thus, the constitution of the ethical subject cannot be understood as a mere emanation of the self, but as an answer, an action,
to the necessity of the other, that is, as a negation of the negation. So the answer is directed toward the subject. In this
way, the action is not dissociated from the constitution, or recognition, of the ethical subject. Therefore, any universality
that deals with the other as if he had dignity would just leave the other plunged
in his disgrace, and the self that is acquainted with the other could just abandon itself to the satisfaction of its assumed
ethical possession.
How then are the ethical subject and his action constituted? In Benjamin, the starting point of the constitution of
man as an ethical subject is the needed man; one making his cause our own as an ethical impulse, and one asserting the answer
to the necessity of the other as a political action. The cry of the needed one - expression of suffering and injustice - is
the universality of the answer to the actual misery and injustice. There is no ethical subject except as an impulse and an
answer to that demand. In the history of mankind, in which unhappiness constitutes a fundamental feature, a certain human
reaction has become apparent: the experience of its negativity.
For Benjamin, ethics is politics. The ethical impulse is the content of the political ideals and values - justice,
freedom, equality and solidarity. Benjamin’s concern is to bring compassion and politics into a dialectical relationship,
one that manifests itself in configurations of one into the other and vice versa - a theological relationship in Benjamin’s
language.
Benjamin’s politics starts not from a matter of reason but from the ‘history of suffering’
and its negativity. This fact is that the man of flesh and blood suffers, is hungry, suffers from injustice; where man is
not seen as a subject deprived of his dignity, which belongs to him, but as an object of a blind historical situation. Because
the other one does not yet have dignity, there can only be a relationship of solidarity, whose sense is not other but to actualize
the demand of dignity. This sense of solidarity that necessarily goes with experience makes Benjamin’s philosophy a
political ethics. This experience as solidarity is not merely satisfied
with the Kantian imperative that says just not to obstruct the other as an end in itself, but rather compels us to remove
the obstacles that limit the other to recover his dignity. That active attitude is what Benjamin understands as political
action, as historical praxis.
Benjamin understands the experience of solidarity as a situation of injustice and misery that the other suffers, situation
to which we are indissolubly bound up – ‘there is a secret agreement between past generations and the present
one […] our coming was expected on earth’ [Benjamin 1940, thesis II, 390]. There is an ethical relationship between
the subject deprived of his dignity and the self that discovers itself dependent on the other – ‘Only for the
sake of the hopeless ones have we been given hope’ [Benjamin 1913-26, 356] - where an ethical impulse occurs only when
man professes his commitment to feelings of indignation, compassion, and solidarity. This means that we belong to a tradition
of hope, and we burden the history that the present displays. In Mate’s words:
But somebody is “expecting us:” he has been previous to us, but he had not stayed behind but
has moved forwards. Who is that? The victims, the army of losers, all those that cannot have peaceful rest because they have
been deprived of their dignity. If they wait for us is because they expect something in return, they have some pending rights
that we must settle [Mate 1991, 154].
In sum, Benjamin’s concept of experience as solidarity is what gives ethical substance to politics, or in other
words, it is a ‘political temporalization of experience’ [Osborne 2000,
59], where the character of the present - its political action-generating - is determined by its relation to a specific past
- its ethical impulse. Thus, a specific idea of the past is the cause of the experience as solidarity – ‘idea of the past, which is the concern of history’ – to wit, the idea of justice. This
is the dialectics that redefines historical experience as solidarity, solidarity as politics; political praxis as ethical actualization, ethical actualization as praxis.
References
Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. In The
Complete Works of Aristotle, Vol. 2. Ed. Jonathan Barnes. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984.
Benjamin, Walter. ‘Goethe’s Elective Affinities’ (1919-22). In Selected Writings. Vol. 1.
Ed. Marcus Bullock and Michael W. Jennings. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996.
___. The Arcades Project (1927-1940). Trans. Howard Eiland and Kevin McLaughlin.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999.
___. ‘On the Concept of History’ (1940). In Selected Writings,
Vol. 4. Ed. Howard Eiland and Michael W. Jennings. Trans. Edmund Jephcott et al. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2003.
Mate, Reyes. La Razón de los Vencidos. Barcelona: Anthropos, 1991.
Radnoti, Sandor. ‘Benjamin’s Politics.’ In Telos, 37 (fall 1978): 63-81.
Schelling, F.W.J. Sämtliche Werke. Vol. 8. Ed. K.F.A. Schelling. Stuttgart:
Cotta, 1856-1861.
Alfredo Lucero-Montano holds a Master in Philosophy from San Diego State University.